Set: Difference between revisions
No edit summary |
|||
Line 14: | Line 14: | ||
=== The traditional concept === | === The traditional concept === | ||
In standard mathematics, there is supposed to be a single object called "''the''" empty set. | In standard mathematics, there is supposed to be a single object called "''the''" empty set. Most sets in standard mathematics are not unique in this manner. The empty set is called "the" empty set because it is unique up to unique isomorphism. Of course, that imaginary object is not what Objective Mathematics means by the concept of an empty set. | ||
Nevertheless, it is sometimes valid to use the phrase "''the'' empty set" in Objective Mathematics. It is valid in the same sense that it is valid to say "the cat" or "the car." Namely, if one has a specific empty set in mind, and wishes to refer to that empty set and not another one, he may call it "the empty set." | |||
== Relations among sets == | |||
In this section, I will describe some relations<ref group="note">In this context, standard mathematics would use the phrase "operations on sets" or "constructions in the category of sets," rather than "relations among sets." </ref> among sets. That is, I will describe ways in which some sets (possibly along with [[functions]] between them) can be used to ''identify''<ref group="note">In this context, standard mathematics uses the word "construct" instead of the word "identify."</ref> other sets. | |||
== Infinite sets == | == Infinite sets == | ||
Line 44: | Line 38: | ||
=== But what about all the ''practical'' infinite sets? === | === But what about all the ''practical'' infinite sets? === | ||
Standard mathematics makes use of infinite sets, and many of those infinite sets appear to be practical. Some examples are the set of all [[integers]], the set of all [[fractions]], infinite [[sequences]], etc. Objective Mathematics accepts that integers, fractions, and sequences are [[Concept|concepts]], and useful ones at that. But it denies that integers, fractions, etc. are infinite sets. | Standard mathematics makes use of infinite sets, and many of those infinite sets appear to be practical. Some examples are the set of all [[integers]], the set of all [[fractions]], infinite [[sequences]], etc. Objective Mathematics accepts that integers, fractions, and sequences are [[Concept|concepts]], and useful ones at that. But it denies that integers, fractions, etc. are infinite sets. | ||
== Notes == | |||
<references group="note" /> | |||
== References == | == References == |
Revision as of 23:21, 3 February 2024
A set is an irreducible primary, and therefore can only be defined ostensively.
A circular way of defining set, which may nonetheless provide some insight, is that a set is a collection of similar existents, considered together as a whole.
Sets are sometimes called groups (e.g. in ITOE), but Objective Mathematics reserves that terminology for a different concept.
Empty sets
An empty set (not "the" empty set; see below) is one way of viewing the concept of nothing. The concept of "nothing" may seem impossible or invalid. Concepts need to have referents, and yet everything is something; there is no thing which is nothing. How can this be? ITOE explains[1]
["Nothing"] is strictly a relative concept. It pertains to the absence of some kind of concrete. The concept “nothing” is not possible except in relation to “something.” Therefore, to have the concept “nothing,” you mentally specify—in parenthesis, in effect—the absence of a something, and you conceive of “nothing” only in relation to concretes which no longer exist or which do not exist at present.
You can say “I have nothing in my pocket.” That doesn’t mean you have an entity called “nothing” in your pocket. You do not have any of the objects that could conceivably be there, such as handkerchiefs, money, gloves, or whatever. “Nothing” is strictly a concept relative to some existent [sic] concretes whose absence you denote in this form.
Examples
If one has no books on one's table, it may be said that he has an empty set of books on his table.
If there are no more days left until March 3rd, 2055 (i.e. if it is currently March 3rd, 2055), then it may be said that the set of days until March 3rd is empty.
The traditional concept
In standard mathematics, there is supposed to be a single object called "the" empty set. Most sets in standard mathematics are not unique in this manner. The empty set is called "the" empty set because it is unique up to unique isomorphism. Of course, that imaginary object is not what Objective Mathematics means by the concept of an empty set.
Nevertheless, it is sometimes valid to use the phrase "the empty set" in Objective Mathematics. It is valid in the same sense that it is valid to say "the cat" or "the car." Namely, if one has a specific empty set in mind, and wishes to refer to that empty set and not another one, he may call it "the empty set."
Relations among sets
In this section, I will describe some relations[note 1] among sets. That is, I will describe ways in which some sets (possibly along with functions between them) can be used to identify[note 2] other sets.
Infinite sets
Objective Mathematics says that infinite sets are an invalid notion. In essence, this is because an infinite set does not refer to anything that can be perceived. Unsurprisingly, this disconnection from reality causes many derivative problems for infinite sets. The concept of Objective Mathematics which is closest to that of an infinite set is that of a concept.
The traditional concept
Standard mathematics says that a set is infinite if there exist functions which are injective but not surjective.
To demonstrate how absurd this is, and how much it conflicts with real-life, consider David Hilbert's thought experiment[2] about what it would be like if a hotel had infinitely many rooms. Suppose that there is an infinite hotel, where each room has a room number . This hotel is completely full; every room is occupied. But unlike real hotels, if a new guest comes in and asks for a hotel room, the concierge can make room for him, even though the hotel is already full. The concierge need merely request that every hotel guest move to the room next door: if a guest's room number is , he should move to room number . (This is the key step: here the concierge is applying a function which is injective but not surjective). After everyone changes rooms, the hotel has space, because room number 1 is no longer occupied. Note that all of the guests still have their same room.
But what about extended objects?
There are an unlimited number of points on an extended object. It may therefore seem like there should be, for any extended object O, such a thing as "the set of all points on O." Since there are unlimited number of points on O, doesn't that mean that there is an infinite set?
To see why that is wrong, we must examine more carefully what is meant by a point. In some contexts, the concept of a point is used to identify a physical object. For example, the reader can easily identify a point in this picture [TODO]. In other contexts, the concept of a point is used to identify a location whose only distinguishing characteristic is that it is the place where one is focusing one's attention. For an example, the reader should try to focus on one specific point on a blank and featureless area of his wall.
We may now see the subtlety with the idea of "the set of all points on O." There may be some points on O which are physical, i.e. points which can be perceptually distinguished from the rest of O. But in order for such points to be perceived, they must necessarily have a finite size, so there can only be finitely many of them. As for those points on O which are non-physical, it is true that there is no limit on how many could exist. But since the concretes in question are merely objects of one's focus, rather than objects in reality, they do not actually exist until one chooses to focus. And one can only ever focus on finitely many points of O. We have thus refuted the idea that there exist infinitely many points on O.
But what about all the practical infinite sets?
Standard mathematics makes use of infinite sets, and many of those infinite sets appear to be practical. Some examples are the set of all integers, the set of all fractions, infinite sequences, etc. Objective Mathematics accepts that integers, fractions, and sequences are concepts, and useful ones at that. But it denies that integers, fractions, etc. are infinite sets.